School of Historical and Philosophical Studies - Theses

Permanent URI for this collection

Search Results

Now showing 1 - 10 of 61
  • Item
    Thumbnail Image
    Jawa : an adaptive strategy in a marginal environment
    Porter, Anne. (University of Melbourne, 1985)
  • Item
  • Item
    Thumbnail Image
    Prostitution and the state in Victoria, 1890-1914
    Arnot, Margaret ( 1986)
    The later decades of the nineteenth and the early decades of the twentieth centuries were marked by considerable change in Victorian society. Rapid urban expansion and industrialization were among the most profound of these developments. They resulted in increasing problems of urban over-crowding, poverty, sanitation and, despite the youth of the cities, decay. Those in power began to see these urban problems as being partly related to the nature of working-class life, so sought to control aspects of working-class culture to an unprecedented degree. During this period, legislation relating to liquor, tobacco, drugs, and gambling, for example, were brought into effect for the first time or became more intrusive. Street life was becoming increasingly regulated. In 1891, for example, amendments to the Victorian Police Offences Act made important changes to the social construction of anti-social behaviour and placed increased power in the hands of the police and legal institutions to control the behaviour of individuals in public places. As part of this development, soliciting prostitution was made an offence for the first time. Women, too, had become subversive. Feminists demanded the vote, increased educational opportunities and threatened the established power differential between the sexes. At the same time, legislation was being passed and medical practices were emerging which increasingly impinged upon women's bodies and upon the areas of women's traditional power - life itself and child life. Kerreen Reiger has traced the increasing attempts to professionalize and rationalize family life, resulting in greater intrusion into the lives of women in relation to childbirth and motherhood.' Increasing attempts to control prostitution in Australia date from this same period, and can be seen as part of these processes. It was from the 1860s that an edifice of laws was constructed. Firstly, legislators were concerned with how women were forced into prostitution (procuring), the relationships between women working in prostitution and their children, and the spread of venereal disease. Later, from the 1890s, there was a new spate of legislation related to soliciting, the ownership and management of brothels, procuring, and living on the earnings of prostitution. During the same period a centralized, bureaucratized police force, which was crucially involved in the increasing control of prostitution, was established in Victoria. The prison system, too, became more organized and intrusive. By the later part of this period the move toward greater state intrusion into the area of prostitution was clear; the years 1890 to 1914 have been chosen for detailed study. This period was marked at the beginning by important new amendments to the Police Offences and Crimes Acts in 1891 and at the end by the advent of the First World War, which created new contexts and problems. (From Introduction)
  • Item
  • Item
    Thumbnail Image
    Realism
    O'Flaherty, Sidney Michael ( 1989)
    This thesis argues for realism. It argues for realism on the basis of considerations of language. It does not assert that we can know realism to be correct, so it is realism as a possible position. It does argue that we can have every confidence that what our language tells us about our world is accurate (with an important proviso in the realm of science). Consequently, I dub it a "possible strong realism". It is a form of realism because it argues fur the proposition that our language is the world at one remove, that it metaphorically is the world, and that our use of language is good evidence both that we are getting the way the world is, right, and that there is a world in what we describe. If there was not a world, we could not make sense of the aboutness of our speech, and, more importantly, if there was not a world which was independent of our possible formulation of it, and larger than our formulation of it, then, once again, no sense could be made of our seeming to make sense. But there is no one-to-one formal correspondence between our terms and "object," in the world; there is no causal, physical link between the two at an individual level, since language is not literal. It is a strong realism because it argues for a full-blooded acceptance of language as being an accurate account of the world at one remove, namely metaphorically. It is important to note that language is not a picture of the world in the conventional sense, because a picture is a literal representation, and language is not a picture. It is the world at one remove. Or I argue that it is best taken that way. We make the inference from language to the world. It is a possible realism because it asserts that we can never know that realism is correct, because to think that one can know that it is correct is to seek to be on both sides of the line at once, to be at once inside language and outside it, and that we cannot be. That might seem to make us prisoners of language, but a possible strong realism allows the possibility that when we speak of that which is ostensibly about us, there is an isomorphism which means that when we do so speak, we can be confident that our speech or marks are capturing something of the way the world is apart from our concerns, concepts and terms. only on the basis of such a supposition can we make sense of the world postulated within our language. Or at least this is what I shall argue. But this isomorphism, this assertion of accuracy, can only be a possibility, and by possibility I don't mean the possibility of error. What I mean is that we can never know realism to be correct, on the account of realism here given, since part of what realism means is that there may be parts of reality which will always escape us. In' chapter 1, I argue that we can make a transcendental inference from language to the world. It is easier to make if the meaning of our words is not wholly determined in their use, but the inference can still be made if use does exhaust meaning. I argue that use does not in fact exhaust meaning. T contend that a view of language as "peculiar metaphor" is a good base on which to build realism, as it avoids on the one hand the eliminative view of the meaning of words being solely in their use, and, on the other hand, it also avoids the insistent attractiveness of language as picture (the contrast between the later and earlier Wittgenstein). Language as metaphor has the added virtues of being a good model for the explanation of the growth of language, and introducing a mental element to meaning. Chapter 2 turns to a consideration of the status of sub-microscopic scientific entities through looking mainly at the anti-realism of van Fraassen with respect to those entities, and argues that the distinction between observables and unobservables, on which distinction he relies for his anti-realism, will not stand up. Possible strong realism asserts that, as well as good metaphor within language, there can be bad metaphor, and the metaphor of language with respect to the macro objects of everyday life is inappropriately applied to the alleged "existence" of the sub-microscopic "particles" of science. The model of existence at the macro level is an inappropriate one at the micro level. Language can be systematically misleading with respect to the world, or part of it, because 0f our nature, as well as systematically leading. Chapter 3 explores the contrasting views of Devitt and Taylor. Along the way, T contrast Devitt's view to Quine's, in order to show the difference in the importance accorded to ontology. A possible strong realism argues for the world of objects that Devitt wants, at least at the macro level, but starts from a different point, from language. Starting from a different point, it comes to a different conclusion, that, while we can be ontologically confident, as Quine claims, to talk of the independent and objective existence of objects is to be a metaphysical realist. The view of language that I advocate does net go outside language for its confidence. My realism also argues that everyday objects at least are not theoretical constructions, as Quine claims Its starting point is once again different from Taylor's, whose position seems to imply that we move from the truth of sentences to the constitution of the world. That is veering too close to anti-realism, and the "truth" used in my realism is both co-extensive with, yet larger than, Taylor's epistemic truth.
  • Item
  • Item
  • Item
  • Item
  • Item